I realised recently that it’s been about a month and a half since I posted. Woops! In my defence: I’ve been attempting to finish the 80 pages I need to write for this term’s coursework, while preparing presentations, and organising and attending conferences. It’s heaven: the days are chock-full of Philosophy!!!
I recently got to attend the Pacific APA, and had a blast. Luckily for me, I got to present my paper the very first day, only two hours after the conference began. After that, I was able to sit back and enjoy the show. I got to see Neal Tognazzini talk about moral responsibility and stage theory, Casey Karbowski talk about the argument from vagueness for unrestricted composition, and Danny Korman discuss naive (or, better: natural) ontology. And of course, there was JSchaff discussing Monism, Schroeder on desires, and six hours in one day about Relativism.
All of this was taking place between periods of hanging out with Philosophers at restaurants, bars, coffee shops, Portland’s famous bookstore, and even a music show. I’m delighted - I got to catch up with several of my friends, and meet a bunch of people as well. And I learned a lot! It struck me, as it usually does after conferences like this one, that we’re very lucky to have such a thriving community of hella-nice, wicked-smart people.
Something semi-amusing: I was scheduled to leave Portland Sunday the 26th, so (figuring I’d sleep on the plane) I let myself stay up all night Saturday. But my plane was overbooked, so I was given a $400 check and sent back to spend a few extra hours at the conference. It was fantastic, I got to go to three more talks! The only unfortunate part of the surprise was that, in my sleep-deprived state, I asked a really stupid question in a session about Lewis. My first question at an APA session, ever, and it was so bad. Even hazy and incoherent as I was, I could tell that much. Oh well, I suppose it could be worse: for instance, I could have asked a really bad question when not sleep deprived!
Usually after these conferences I go through withdrawls, moping around and such. But getting back to Rutgers, I found that the prospectives were already visiting! It was great to get to meet them: they’re all really smart, excited and talkative. I’m looking forward to hanging out with them (or, at least, with whoever I get to - I'm not sure how many will end up in this area) in the coming years.
For now, it’s down to work getting papers finished for classes, and a presentation prepared for later this month. Also, I’m taking the weekend off to go up to the University of Connecticut for a conference on conditionals - I’m excited to get to attend, it looks like a lot of fun!
As for some of what I’ve been working on: I recently finished a draft of a paper on the At-At account of motion. In the paper, I claim that we can’t accept the At-At account as a claim about what it means to move, since it gives the wrong results in cases where something spatially multilocated persists. Consider, for instance, a case where something is located at R1 at T1, then time-travels to R2 at T2, then time-travels back to R2 at T1, then skips ahead again to R1 at T2. Intuitively, this case involves a lot of motion. But there’s a relevantly similar case where an object is multilocated at T1, wholly located at both R1 and R2, and is also multilocated at T2 in the same way. It simply persists (though it’s temporally gappy) in R1 and in R2. Intuitively, there isn’t motion in this case. But the only thing we’ve changed between the cases is the causal relations the thing bears to itself at various regions. And the At-At account, in its elegant reduction of motion to something simple and non-mysterious, has no room for such considerations.
I’ve still got some work to do on the paper, looking at various responses to the case. (E.g., denying it’s possible, indexing motion to regions, and cashing out what we might need to appeal to if those responses don’t work.) And I also need to write out some of the benefits of making our account of motion sensitive to these extra considerations - for instance, our intuitions falter in some intermediate cases (e.g., when a thing is wholly at R1 at T1, and wholly at R1 at T2 and also wholly at R2 at T2. Does it move?), and I can give a nice explanation for why (namely, the case above is underdescribed; we need to know more about the relations the thing bears to itself at the various regions before we can tell whether it moves).
There's other stuff I'm thinking about as well, though I want to work on it more before I post on it. But I'm having tons of fun -- grad school is really incredible.
Alright, I'm off for the night. Best wishes on a great spring term!
Hey Shieva,
I've been thinking a bit about the "at-at" theory of velocity, too, for this paper I'm drafting on vectorial properties. So, keep the posts like these coming!
Re: Your counterexample. There might be a simple (or simplistic?) response at hand for the proponent of the "at-at" theory. Suppose in both cases, we were to cut a notch in whatever fills region R1 at time T1, and then let both systems evolve. In the second case, there would be no notch in whatever fills region R2 at T2. But in the first case, there would be a notch in both regions at T1. Now, couldn't the proponent of the "at-at" theory appeal to these sorts of considerations in order to differentiate the two cases?
Posted by: Alex Skiles | April 06, 2006 at 10:59 AM
The second-to-last line of the previous line should read as follows (paying attention to the *-*):
<< But in the first case, there would be a notch in both regions at *T2.* >>
What this should make clear is that the difference between the two cases is *not* a kinematic one, so any theory of velocity should be able to differentiate the two cases. (Though of course, and oddly enough, what I wrote *would* be accurate in the case of backwards time travel!)
Posted by: Alex Skiles | April 06, 2006 at 01:58 PM
Hey Alex,
Good to hear from you - I hope things are going well at Notre Dame!
Regarding your response, I'm not yet seeing how it'll help the At-At theorist. If my case is possible, the account as commonly stated is false. Here's the formulation:
Necessarily, for any x, x moves iff there exist spaces s1 and s2, and times t1 and t2, such that s1 is distinct from s2, t1 is distinct from t2, and x is at s1 at t1 and at s2 at t2.
(There are questions about how to understand the 'at' in the account, and I argue in the paper that the most plausible way to understand it is as 'wholly at', or at least, 'has a temporal part wholly at'. It then gets a bit messier, because I need to describe temporal parts in a way that allows them to be multilocated (I argue that we need that, too). But anyway, the idea is straightforward enough.)
The considerations you appealed to seem to be outside the scope of what the above account can take as relevant to whether any given object moves.
In the paper, I'll discuss a response some may be tempted toward: keep the spirit of the account while avoiding these worries, by relativising motion to regions. It's not so unnatural, after all, since we relativise other properties to regions to avoid the problem of spatial intrinsics for spatially multilocated entities (for a discussion of the problem of spatial intrinsics, see (among other sources) Hud Hudson's 2006 book, The Metaphysics of Hyperspace). One may think that by relativising to regions, they can sneak in the extra considerations the At-At account seems to be overlooking, because those considerations will determine (or at least, partially determine) which regions we relativise to. I think this won't work, but that's an argument I'll have to leave for a future post!
Posted by: Shieva | April 06, 2006 at 04:30 PM
Hey Shieva,
A few questions/comments:
First: Think of my suggestion as a modification of the "relativizing motion to regions" response, where now we're using intrinsic properties of the region occupiers to fix the kinematical facts, rather than the regions themselves.
Second: Now, technically you're right that for the proponent of the "at-at" theory, these considerations are "beyond the scope" of her main account. But so what? She can appeal to whatever she needs in order to differentiate the two cases, as long as it doesn't involve talking about truly instantaneous velocities and the like.
Third: No proponent of the "at-at" theory would say that simply being located in distinct spatiotemporal regions suffices for motion, basically because spatiotemporal multilocation is insufficient to guarantee that whatever is multilocated at these regions has a definite velocity. So I'm curious: From whom are you taking this formulation of the "at-at" theory?
Fourth: I'm not sure from where your intuitions about the two cases are coming. Why should we think that Case #1 involves motion? (Would we want to count *forward* time travel as motion, too?) And why should we think that Case #2 involves no motion at all?
Posted by: Alex Skiles | April 07, 2006 at 12:34 PM
Hey Shieva, I'm Jonathan. I've been reading your blog for a couple of years. I used to be more active in commenting than I have been of late. I just wanted to say hello and let you know that I'm transferring to Rutgers this fall (following Ernie Sosa from Brown). I'm looking forward to it. So: see you around!
Posted by: Jonathan Ichikawa | April 18, 2006 at 02:03 PM